Pages

Eleanor Roosevelt, 1958

'Where, after all, do universal human rights begin? In small places, close to home -- so close and so small that they cannot be seen on any map of the world. Yet they are the world of the individual person... Unless these rights have meaning there, they have little meaning anywhere. Without concerted citizen action to uphold them close to home, we shall look in vain for progress in the larger world.' Eleanor Roosevelt, 1958

The Small Places has moved...

The Small Places has moved to a new home here, including all the old posts. Any posts after 6th March 2014 will appear on the new website, but old posts are preserved here so that URLs linking here continue to work. Please check out the new site.

Monday 6 June 2011

What is mental capacity?


Today I’ve decided to just put up some notes I’ve been making on “mental capacity” as a legal concept.  They weren’t really written to be a blog post, but I don’t think there’s any harm in sharing them.  It’s not going to contain any great revelations, but I found it interesting to chart how the concept has unfolded from the time of the Law Commissions’ first reports on mental capacity (available under ‘M’ on Bailii).  I’m not a philosopher, but I do find some concepts from philosophy helpful to unpick the ways in which the concept has been used.  If this kind of “abstract” piece isn’t not your cup of tea, maybe come back later in the week for comment on the Neary ruling when it’s out.

Different tests of capacity

The Law Commission discussed different ‘mental capacity’ type concepts in other jurisdictions.  ‘Status’, or ‘category’, approaches make global (or near-global) attributions of decisional capacity on the basis of membership of a particular diagnostic category or legally defined group.  For instance, a status approach might say that anyone within a particular age bracket, or with a particular medical diagnosis, lacks capacity in all matters.   They also noted that the legal status of being a ‘patient’ of the Court of Protection (in its pre-MCA incarnation) effectively deprived them of all contractual capacity ‘whether or not as a matter of fact the patient actually had such capacity’ [3.3]. They rejected status approaches on the basis that they oversimplify the question of whether a person has decisional capacity and they ‘tend to undermine respect for individual rights’ [2.43].  Certain kinds of status approaches are explicitly precluded by s2(3) Mental Capacity Act 2005 (MCA).

Outcome based approaches attribute capacity on the basis of the outcome of a particular decision.  The Law Commission gave this pretty short shrift, saying:
‘A decision which is inconsistent with the views and values of the assessor, or rejects conventional wisdom is by definition incompetently made’
and
‘This penalises individuality and demands conformity at the expense of personal autonomy’ [3.4]. 
They reported, however, that many respondents felt that doctors were applying an ‘outcome’ approach, whereby a person was taken to lack capacity if they rejected a course of treatment which the doctor advised.  Section 1(4) MCA can be seen as a caution against ‘outcome’ based approaches.  I'll consider below whether the MCA formulation allows 'outcome based' approaches in by the back door.

In the event, the Law Commission proposed what they called a ‘functional’ approach, on the basis that it was the most strongly supported by respondents to their consultation, and had ‘the merit of being the approach adopted by most of the established tests in English law’ [3.5].  This ‘functional approach’ was combined with a diagnostic threshold, giving rise to what is referred to in the code of practice as the ‘two-stage test of capacity’ (p41). Unlike status or category approaches, a functional approach is ‘decision specific’ – a person’s mental capacity can only be determined by reference to their ability to make the decision in hand. 

The first stage of capacity assessment: Invoking a diagnostic threshold

Section 2(1) MCA states that a person lacks capacity if they are unable to make a decision ‘because of an impairment of, or a disturbance in the functioning of, the mind or brain.’  The Law Commission considered arguments for and against including a diagnostic threshold [3.10-3.14].  Arguments against included that it might encourage a purely ‘status’ approach to capacity, that it was stigmatising, and that a medical label was in any case superfluous to the legal and moral issues at stake.  The Law Commission felt that the second ‘functional’ stage of the test would discourage a status-only approach, meanwhile, they felt, not having a diagnostic threshold would ‘places too heavy a burden on the functional test... this test is not easy to define or to apply, particularly as to the degree of incapacity which is required’.  They regarded one benefit of the diagnostic threshold as increasing:
...the involvement of people with suitable specialist qualifications in the determination of whether intervention is necessary in an individual case, and what kind of intervention is most appropriate. [3.11]
The formulation quite deliberately reinforces the status of medical and health professional evidence in these matters.  The Law Commission felt a diagnostic test had a role to play ‘in ensuring that the test is stringent enough not to catch large numbers of people who make unusual or unwise decisions’ [3.8]; thus it is medical and health professionals who are charged in law with demarcating the boundaries of madness, non-pathological deviance and eccentricity.  There’s probably a lot that could be said about this decision from governmentality and critical psychiatry perspectives, but I won’t get into that here.  The diagnostic threshold has an influence on the way individuals are described in cases: almost always the first thing we learn about them is their diagnosis, and very often for people with learning disabilities that rather dubious concept – their mental age.  I always wonder how far 'mental age' as a construct has achieved such prominence in case law  because it seems to tacitly sanction paternalistic interventions that we would regard as acceptable in the lives of children, but generally not adults.

The second stage of capacity assessment: The ‘functional test’

The ‘functional test’ of capacity is set out in s3 MCA.  I noticed that in at least one of the Law Commission reports they refer to this as a ‘cognitive’ test.  I am glad they have dropped this terminology. I doubt many psychologists who use the term ‘cognitive’ would mean it in this way, and I share many of the reservations about ‘cognitive’ approaches to clinical psychology expressed by discursive psychologists.  Cognitive approaches can pay insufficient attention to someone's embodied and social context, and offer false claims of neutrality regarding the cultural and political content of the issue under discussion.  By contrast, discursive psychologists acknowledge the 'constructed' nature of psychological concepts, and emphasise that in understanding concepts like 'mental capacity' we should explore what these concepts enable us to do.

There have been attempts to look for ‘cognitive correlates’ of mental capacity by researchers (e.g. Palmer, 2004), but I personally doubt whether these are well founded in principle.  No doubt soon enough we shall see neuroscientists claim to have found the areas of the brain that light up when a person “has capacity”; I hope these claims are treated with the critical caution they deserve.  A key problem with such reductionistic approaches, as we shall see, is that the concept of mental capacity may take into account many features of a person’s circumstances, and many background normative orientations, that would not be picked up in the kinds of tests and scales favoured in neuropsychology.

So, the functional test says that a person is to be regarded as unable to make a decision if they are unable to understand, retain or use or weigh the information relevant to the decision.  It also includes a fourth criterion: the ability to communicate a decision; this was explicitly intended to ensure the MCA covered cases of locked-in syndrome, but may also be important conceptually and legally for people who have limited communication abilities.  Section 3(2) MCA reiterates the message of s1(3), that the most appropriate means to impart the information relevant to a decision should be sought, and a person should be supported in taking the decision for themselves as far as is practicable.  Section 4(3) MCA acknowledges that the capacity to take a particular decision can develop or fluctuate, and requires assessors to consider whether the decision could be taken at a later point when a person may have gained, or regained, capacity.

Epistemic and value commitments in understanding, using and weighing information

In some respects the MCA appears to be a paragon of liberal tolerance of any eccentric or minority views which might inform decisions, but the picture may be more complex than that.  The capacity assessor will need to elucidate exactly what ‘information relevant to the decision’ needs to be understood, retained and weighed in order to make it.  Section 3(4) MCA says that this information ‘includes information about the reasonably foreseeable consequences of (a)deciding one way or another, or (b)failing to make the decision’.  It is hard to see how this aspect of the test could avoid incorporating some subjective judgments as to what information is relevant, and some epistemic commitments about what information is ‘true’ and what consequences are reasonably foreseeable.  The recent debates around capacity to consent to sex illustrate the subjective nature of the 'relevance' point nicely; in D Borough Council v AB the doctor held it to be important that a person understands the nature of consent itself, and the emotional consequences of sex – Mostyn J, deciding, did not.

The epistemic commitments required by a test of capacity to make a particular decision may also be contentious.  Neil Allen has written a great article on this topic, called Is Capacity “In Sight”? (pdf).  He discusses a quote by Munby J in Local Authority X v MM & Anor (No. 1) [2007]:
If one does not “believe” a particular piece of information then one does not, in truth, “comprehend” or “understand” it, nor can it be said that one is able to “use” or “weigh” it. In other words, the specific requirement of belief is subsumed in the more general requirements of understanding and of ability to use and weigh information.”32' [81]
The belief criterion may at times be contentious, particularly if a person is required to have ‘insight’ into having a particular medical diagnosis in order to demonstrate that they have the capacity to refuse treatment for it.  A person may likewise have to concur with treating professionals that a particular treatment would be beneficial, if they are to be regarded as ‘understanding’ the information sufficiently to reject it.  I can also imagine circumstances where a person could be expected to reject certain beliefs of their own to demonstrate understanding, for instance, that homeopathy will not cure cancer.  Allen discusses some interesting examples, including the famous case of Re C (Adult: Refusal of Medical Treatment) [1994] 1 All E.R. 819 (which I can’t find a free copy of online, any links gratefully accepted).  The case Re C concerned a man with a diagnosis of schizophrenia who was under the delusion that he was a great doctor.  He believed that God would cure his gangrenous foot and that medical treatments were calculated to destroy his body, although the doctors believed amputation was the only way to save his life.  The judge found that despite C’s beliefs, he had capacity as there was no evidence of ‘any direct link between C's refusal and his persecutory delusions’.  I heard through word of mouth, although I am not sure if it is correct, that C did in fact go on to survive even without the surgery.

I saw a great talk by Jules Holroyd at a CRASSH event where she discussed possible value commitments underpinning the requirement to ‘weigh’ information; in particular whether anorexic patients might be considered to lack the capacity to refuse treatment if they did not weigh the risk of death or disability sufficiently highly.  Of course some beliefs and values that are not shared by the majority, or by “experts” in a particular field, may nevertheless be accorded respect in law.  This is especially true if they are religious or culturally held by a recognised group.  The legal issue is not whether a person bases their decision on ‘incorrect’ or disputed information, or that they value something in an unusual way, rather the reason for their doing so.  If it is felt to be firmly grounded in a religious or cultural conviction, it will not pass the diagnostic criterion that the failure to believe a piece of information that the capacity assessor holds relevant is caused by an impairment of the mind or brain.  Of course, danger may lurk when 'denialism' or a religious belief are treated as symptomatic of a mental disorder in themselves.

Mental capacity is relational and contextual

“Mental capacity” sounds like a state of affairs in somebody’s head, but it is clear from the case law that the approach taken by judges in the Court of Protection places considerable emphasis on a person’s context and relationships in determining capacity.  A person’s relationships with others may be seen to either improve, or impair, their mental capacity.  The recent case of V v R (2011) is a good example of where relationships and situation have been held to increase mental capacity.  The case concerned a young woman, V, who had suffered a traumatic brain injury.  She was pursuing a compensation claim against the insurers of a vehicle that had knocked her down; her mother had expressed concerns that V lacked litigation capacity, and it was decided prudent by V’s own counsel to settle the matter in case the issue came up later on in proceedings.  According to the testimony of V’s mother, V lacked the concentration required to read legal documents, was prone to making impulsive decisions, and any decisions she did take she took on the advice of her mother.  “The reality” according to V’s mother's testimony “was that she and not the claimant would make any material decision.” [29].  The experts were divided in their views.  In the end, the judge concluded that the difficulties that V might have in making decisions ‘are capable of being ameliorated, if not entirely overcome, by the careful and structured support that the statute contemplates’, and thus V was held to have capacity.  The finding that V had capacity was thus not based on what V could achieve in isolation, but on the practical reality that she went through all major decisions with her mother and based them upon her advice, that her mother conducted the day to day running of the case, and that this support was likely to continue in the future.  Thus V’s relationships and the context within which the decisions were taken were central to her having ‘mental capacity’, even though on one view the decisions are “actually” being taken by her mother.

In stark contrast to cases like V v R, are cases where a person is found to lack capacity in part as a result of the coercive influence of others upon their decision making.  Perhaps the best known case of this variety is Re T (1992), where a pregnant woman who was Jehovah’s Witness refused a blood transfusion following a road traffic accident.  The court held that T’s refusal of treatment was not valid, in part because she had not been properly informed of the risks, but also because it was felt that her decision arose more from the undue influence of her mother than her own religious convictions.  The case precedes the MCA, and a better example in the light of the Act might be A Primary Care Trust v P (2009).  The case concerned whether P should move out of his mother’s care, as there were concerns about her overbearing influence and disputes arising out of his epilepsy medication.  The judge commented:
It is utterly clear that they have been deeply and, as I find, unhealthily enmeshed in one another, so much so that when speaking to either about themselves or about the other, it is quite impossible to discern whose voice is actually being heard.  [25]
The reasons that I am persuaded that he lacks that capacity are the cumulative force of the following: a) his epilepsy and its impact on his functioning, b) his learning disability which is at the lower end of mild, c) the enmeshed relationship that he has with AH which severely restricts his perspective in terms of being able to think about his future, d) his inability, frequently articulated by him to those who have interviewed him, to visualise any prospect of having a different view to his mother on any subject that matters and his inability to understand what the other aspects of the argument may be in relation to his expressed wishes simply to return and live undisturbed with his mother.  [37]
In both cases the relevant person’s decisions were strongly influenced by the views of their mother, but in one case this was regarded as enhancing their capacity and in the other it was seen as diminishing it.  It is hard to see how this distinction can be maintained without regard to a wider normative framework over whether the mother’s decisions are ultimately beneficial to the relevant person or not.  Both cases may be quite sensible, practical, outcomes but – to me at least – there is something distinctly unsatisfactory about them when considered side by side.  The wisdom of the outcome of the decision is not supposed to affect whether a person has capacity or not, and yet here the substantive distinction seems to be that the support in one case leads to wise decisions, and support in the other is not regarded as doing so by the court.

The legal issue finds a parallel in some philosophy I have been reading.  Whereas traditionally ‘autonomy’ – the ability to govern oneself and one’s actions – has been regarded as centred within an individual, some new approaches stress the relationality of autonomy.  The Stanford Encyclopedia entry on autonomy in political and moral philosophy has a useful summary and references on this approach.  Writings on relational autonomy tend to focus on issues of oppression, but I read an interesting paper by Francis and Silvers exploring how the autonomy of people with cognitive disabilities could be enhanced through relationships with people they called ‘trustees’ who could assist them with reflection and reasoning (the paper is published in this book, or in a special issue of the journal Metaphilosophy).  Francis and Silvers liken the role of a ‘trustee’ to that of a prosthetic limb for an athlete, and they emphasise that all of us are dependent on others and society more generally to help select and refine the information and values upon which we base our decisions.  I have no difficulty accepting the latter point, but I think I do – on reflection – reject the prosthetic parallel.  The problem is that whilst one’s prosthetic may of course enable a person to run, it is unlikely to be said, itself, to do the running.  It is never likely to be attributed with exercising control over a person in the same was that a ‘trustee’ who helps a person to make decisions could be.  It is a tool that is manipulated by the wearer; it does not have the potential to manipulate.

This seems to me to bring us back full circle to the legal problem; we cannot distinguish between a controlling or a supportive influence without reference to both the outcome of the decision made and an extrinsic normative framework about the value of that outcome.  I may be understanding an interesting essay by Jules Holroyd incorrectly, but I wonder if this is related to a point she makes regarding relational autonomy:
...any account [of autonomy that relies upon S standing in a certain social relation] cannot play one of autonomy’s key normative roles: identifying those agents who ought to be protected from (hard) paternalistic intervention. I argue, against objections from Oshana, that there are good reasons for maintaining the notion of autonomy in this role, and thus that such relational conceptions should not be accepted.
This short extract doesn't do justice to Holroyd’s careful article, but I hope my point is at least congruent with hers.  As is illustrated in the case of V v R, what we may want to call relational autonomy can clearly bring very beneficial consequences, but the danger (metaphysical, legal and real) lurks in how we separate off those cases from those of undue influence.

Capacity is experience based

The case law has developed a clear role for experience and learning in capacity.  In D Borough Council v AB Mostyn J found that ‘Alan’ lacked the capacity to consent to sexual relations, but the court directed that attempts should be made to remedy this situation by providing him with sex education, so that he might attain capacity.  For some issues, a lack of life experience might impair someone’s ability to make a decision because the only way to understand the information is through experience.  For example, in A PCT v P (2009) Hedley J says:
...until P has experienced something other than the care of his mother, then he has no opportunity to make true choices about what he wants for himself.  In the circumstances of this case, it is said this can only be achieved by prising him out of his current relationship, significantly curtailing contact and thereby allowing space for the development of a new experience.  Some believe, and leading amongst those is Dr Milnes, his treating psychiatrist, that this will lead to his regaining capacity and it is recognised that should he do so, that may result in a choice to return to AH.  [57]
Clearly it is rather a drastic step to remove someone, involuntarily, from the care of a parent to enhance their mental capacity, and to do so could not be justified by s1(3) MCA alone.  In this case it required the use of the deprivation of liberty provisions of the MCA.  The Law Commission acknowledged in their earliest paper on mental capacity that:
Maximising freedom or providing equality of opportunity goes beyond mere non-interference. It can, for example, imply a need actively to encourage people to take risks. Even if this has adverse short term consequences , there may be long term benefits which cannot be acquired in any other way. Nearly everyone can learn by experience, however slowly. If harm is taken to include under-achievement and lack of fulfillment, are mentally incapacitated people put at greater risk of harm by receiving too much care and protection, or too little?" [1.12]
So capacity can fluctuate not merely according to one’s physiological state, but also according to the opportunities and learning experiences available to a person.  And opportunities to learn and develop may entail taking risks, which need to be balanced against the overall benefits of increased personal autonomy and fulfilment.

Assessment of capacity

I’ll bring these comments to an end now, although this far from exhausts the matter.  I hope I’ve given some convincing reasons to doubt that mental capacity could be determined solely by reference to performance in some laboratory tests or a brain scan!  I just wanted to offer some passing thoughts on the assessment of capacity itself.  We have seen that the case law acknowledges that mental capacity may be contingent on a person’s relationships with those in their immediate circle, their life experience, and their current context, but I think it’s also important to note that it may depend on their relationship with the capacity assessor themselves.  The context of capacity assessment, and the relationship a person has with the person assessing their capacity, may impact on the outcome of the test.  The ability a capacity assessor has to communicate with the relevant person will affect the outcome directly – through MCA s3(1)(d), but also indirectly as they may be less able to communicate to the relevant person the information required for the decision.  This means, for instance, that the level of staff training in communication techniques like Makaton, or even staff turnover, may have a direct effect on the ‘mental capacity’ of people within a particular service.  If a person does not like or trust a particular member of staff or professional, they may not engage in full enough communication to evidence their capacity.  The quality of the relationship may be paramount; we should be concerned, therefore, about the effect of services that do not provide good continuity of care upon a person’s ability to exercise what autonomy they are potentially capable of.

Another issue around capacity assessment that troubles me, particularly where assessments are very formal and undertaken for the purposes of writing a report, is that the assessment process itself may be experienced as an invasion of someone’s privacy.  Even if a person is found to have capacity, the experience of being assessed, having to give reasons for one’s decision, demonstrate that one understands and can weigh certain pieces of information, could potentially be quite intrusive.  It certainly has the potential to place a person in a position of felt inferiority to the person doing the assessing.  I sometimes wonder whether professionals undertaking these kinds of assessment seek the consent of the relevant person first, and of course, whether that assessed person has the capacity to give that consent.  Directions from the court might dispense with the need for that consent, but I do sometimes wonder what happens about capacity assessments that precede court hearings where a person refuses to co-operate with the process.  I heard recently about a case where a person was thought by their solicitor to lack litigation capacity, so the solicitor wrote off to their GP who replied that in their view they lacked it.  I have no idea about the veracity of the claim, but it would trouble me if the relevant person had not consented to that information being disclosed.

It is a wider problem in Court of Protection cases, that I have commented on before in relation to the case D Borough Council v AB, that in striving to ensure people’s rights are upheld, there are dangers that the legal processes themselves may entail other harms which will need to be balanced.  I can see no obvious way around this; I support the principle that people should be protected against harmful decisions they lack the capacity to make, but the very act of assessment that this principle entails may be experienced as oppressive or demeaning by some.  We should approach capacity assessment, therefore, respectfully and with caution, and be careful not to forget s1(2) MCA: the starting point is the presumption that all people, regardless of appearances, have capacity. 

10 comments:

  1. Fantastic post which better verbalises some of my thoughts about capacity. Inherently there is a matter of judgement about what capacity is and sometimes it feels uncomfortable having that 'power' in our hands. In some situations it is fairly straightforward one way or the other, but even bearing in mind the base assumption of capacity - it can sometimes be hard to detach the consequences of the assessment from a base decision of capacity.. or not.
    Especially in some of our risk-averse work settings. For me though, that is the strength of the Act.
    Thanks for sharing these thoughts and this information - it will come in use when considering mental capacity and mental capacity assessments.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Thank you so very much for your post which has helped me to clarify a good many things 'in my own mind'.

    CSCI wrote to me in August 2008, and the following quotes may help answer your question about the way in which CSCI responds to individual complaints. I've deleted names to protect the guilty!

    "(Name of care provider) is responsible for the quality of care at (name of care home)."

    "If you are unhappy with the outcome of the independent investigation undertaken by (name of local authority)'s Primary Care Trust and Social Services, then you can still make a complaint under their local complaints procedures. This can lead to an onward referral to the Local Government Ombudsman in respect of the local authority involvement and the Parliamentary and Health Service Ombudsman in respect of the Primary Care Trust. If you remain unhappy about our conduct following our response to your complaints then you are advised to contact the Complaints Review Service."

    "The Commission for Social Care Inspection is not a complaints agency and we have no statutory poiwers to investigate complaints. The responsibility for handling concerns and complaints about a service rests with the provider. As part of the registration and inspection process, the fitness of the provider's own procedures for handling concerns and complaints were considered and these were found to meet the National Minimum Standards. However, in this instance the manager did not respond as required."

    "We offer our sincere condolences for the passing of (my relative) and the distress that you have been through. We cannot accept responsibility as we have fulfilled our statutory obligations and we will continue to do so through the inspection and enforcement procedures."

    ReplyDelete
  3. Thanks for your comments CB and Care in the UK. I think I was trying to straighten things out in my head with this post, and it's nice that others didn't find it too dry!

    Thanks especially for the info on CSCI and complaints. They also wrote this in an email to me last year:

    'We have no explicit statutory complaints responsibilities under the Care Standards Act 2000, although providers do have to place our name and address in their complaints procedure. This implies that we have a role in receiving complaints about social care services, and for ensuring that those responsible deal with the matter. The Care Standards Act 2000 related regulations and National Minimum Standards (NMS) set out the legal responsibilities and recommended standards for providers’ complaints procedures.'

    So whilst it looks as if they may have an implied role, it's not clearly given in the statute that created the care inspectorate.

    ReplyDelete
  4. Hi Lucy, thanks for being kind enough to share this with me. Got my mental juices flowing.

    Does it matter that I have gotten to know you a little and read this post in that context? Does that impact on my capacity to comment on it? Does it render suspect anything I might say: does it undermine the status of my comments as objective. I hope to all of those it is an emphatic yes.

    The objectification of people into diagnostic labels is something that has long been incompatible with a coherent equalities and human rights framework. That relationship- the so called objective observer- has long been used as a away of undermining those being objectified.

    There is in that relationship a power dynamic that is conveniently denied and the impact of the operation of that power. The observer changes that which is observed, is not a new understanding.

    So contrary to the previous models' assertion that people had capacity or not due to a strictly applied diagnostic criteria, what in fact was happening was that people were being constructed as being without capacity to fit the model. A self fulfilling prophecy. We called it institutionalisation, but socialisation will do as well.

    Understanding capacity as a relationship is to understand that we are in the process of socialising a person into or out of capacity and that must be formalised in our intuitional dealings.

    Medical and care institutions actually value compliance: it's built into their DNA. But compliance is not capacity.

    In the examples you give above the courts have looked at this compliance power issue and in regards to relatively intimate family decision making systems. Again families tend towards homeostasis. A healthy functioning family automatically makes decisions for individuals in a group context.

    A sign of growing up is not to reject the family process but to more fully embrace it as we mature and value it's capacity to enhance personal insight and freedom.

    In the same way it is perfectly natural for us to have been brought up in clan structures and in many ways we are programmed for this collective type of decision making. Nothing in it suggest the individual is lost, in fact the opposite: in relation to the other we know ourself more deeply. We are in all things in becoming. Never finished, a work in progress.

    The solipsism of the isolated mind making rational/objective decisions is a terribly thing. As a psychotherapist my task is most often bringing people back from that sort of despair. Back into a more human, muddy, messy and complicated form of functioning.

    I strongly favour our care, medical and institutional process taking this on board. Dealing with us as the fragile, conflicted, confused and social beings that we are.

    Great post as usual kiddo (sorry been watching Kil Bill 2)

    warm regards

    Noel

    ReplyDelete
  5. Thanks Noel. I think your comments express a lot of my discomfort with the supposed 'neutrality' of the relationships and processes at the heart of the MCA. It's not that I reject the MCA, I think it's a useful tool in many ways, but I do sometimes feel that in all the fanfare around it we ignore the oppressive structures and power dynamics it locks into. Not least of which, of course, diagnostic labels, and 'expert-patient' power relations.

    In relation to 'supported' or 'relational' mental capacity, I definitely agree with you that we should embrace the family and kinship processes that help all of us in our decision making. The difficulty is how the law separates off when that process becomes abusive and limiting, without reference to the 'wisdom' of the decision. To be honest, I don't feel certain that it can; I suspect that judges see the situation, make a decision as to what needs to be done, and apply the MCA as a practical tool that enables them to do that.

    ReplyDelete
  6. Hi Lucy,
    I run a small residential home and our four residents all currently attend a Council run day centre. They have attended this centre for many years and have many friends there (nearly 100 people use the service, approximately 60 a day). They love going there.
    The day centre, like many around the country is currently going through a 4 month period of formal consultation which will mean closure of the current purpose-built building (opened in 1979). The plan is to place people in smaller 'hubs' around the local area in church halls, sports centres or similar, where we are told they will then be part of the community (as if they were not already).
    To get to my point, all the current people with learning disabilities who use this service have been given questionairres to fill in regarding their feelings on what they would like for the future. Independent advocates have been invited to help in this process by the council or individuals can fill in their answers with the help of people at home.
    I, and many of the other carers, are concerned that no thought seems to have gone to the capacity of individuals to understand the long term consequences of their comments when filling in these questionairres. As far as I am aware there have been no assessments with regard to capacity. Do you feel this should have taken place before they were asked to take part in such an important discussion about their future?
    I also have concerns about the advocates for similar reasons to your concerns about people carrying out mental capacity assessments. While well intentioned, the two people involved do not know the individuals well and unfortunately have little experience with this particular client group, so I am not sure how well they are communicating with them (we have not been invited to their meetings).
    There is a great deal of anger here about the proposed closure as the majority of people want the service to remain, with people continuing to access the community from the one central base.
    The powers-that-be have listened to all of this and have told us that that is what people in other areas have told them too and have then said the equivalent of 'but we know best'.A true choice seems to have gone out of the window, as the current centre has been omitted as an option.
    Sorry, I am now rambling off subject, but would really appreciate your opinion on the question of capacity if you have a moment. Thanks!

    ReplyDelete
  7. Hi Anonymous,

    Thanks for your message. You've raised an important issue that I've been musing on for some time: capacity to be consulted. I'm afraid I have no definitive answer for you; to the best of my knowledge it hasn't been raised in any of the court cases around the consultation process, but I think it is a valid concern. If the decision making process around service closure rests on the feedback given by consultees, and there is doubt that the consultees in giving that feedback understood the implications of service closure and the consultation process, then potentially it is flawed. I'm afraid I have no definitive answer to your questions, but here are my thoughts:

    1) Capacity is always presumed, but once a person has reasonable cause to think a person's capacity may be impaired, then a capacity assessment should be done for most decisions. I'm not sure if consultation counts among those decisions though...
    2) If a person lacks capacity, then they should be supported as far as possible to take part in the process. If they lack capacity, they should still be asked about their feelings and preferences, but the weight attached to this is proportionate to their 'residual' mental capacity and the consistency of their views.

    The issue of whether the guidance is adequate and sufficiently easy for consultees to understand was raised in the recent Birmingham consultation case, that might interest you:

    http://www.bailii.org/ew/cases/EWHC/Admin/2011/1147.html

    Particularly - read paragraphs 91 and 93 of that judgment. The Birmingham ruling might be more interesting in a a general sense, if you think the council may not have provided adequate detail to make informed decisions about the replacement service, and also about what alternatives to closure were considered. I should warn you though, even if the consultation process is found to be flawed by a court, there is little stopping a public authority repeating the consultation and making the same decision again...

    Sorry I can't be of more help. If you have strong grounds for doubting people understand the consultation process (or a particular person), then it may be worth writing to the council and asking if they have considered this.

    Cheers, Lucy

    ReplyDelete
  8. Thank you so much Lucy. This is very helpful.
    I do not believe we will be able to prevent the closure of this day centre, but if it has to go I want to help ensure people get a service (or a number of small services) that they really want for the future. Only good consultaion will bring that out and as yet I am not sure that is happening. It all appears to be lip service with decisions already made.
    I am going to discuss your comments with others in our carers group to see how everyone feels about the capacity question and the level of understanding of what is happening.
    I think a letter to the council may also be in order but will find out what the group feel.
    Thank you once again. Your blogs are always so helpful!

    ReplyDelete
  9. Just to update you Lucy, we have discussed the issue of Mental Capacity and consultation with our county council. They say it is not relevent as the people with learning disabilities (who have not been assessed for mental capacity) are not making any decisions, they are merely being asked for their views. Advocates have been working with them to gather in their views. We said it would then depend on how much weight they gave these views when deciding what services should replace the day centre. We have not had a reply from that yet, but I would also be concerned if they were giving no weight at all to the views of these people.Difficult one to get the right balance!

    ReplyDelete
  10. Thanks for the update anonymous. I think getting advocates involved is fantastic. The most important thing is that people's wishes and preferences are heard and acted upon; my concern would be that this consultation was either 'tokenistic', or that it was manipulated in a way to engineer people to affirm choices that suited the organisation rather than the consultees. It is hard - as you say - to get the right balance; hopefully having advocates involved will ensure a truer picture of people's preferences can emerge.

    ReplyDelete